I'm doing some research for my debate about God this week. Prof. DiSilvestro is going to give a version of the moral argument for God. I'll post my notes/essay shortly. Here's a great video from primate researcher Frans de Waal about moral behaviors in chimps.
http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=GcJxRqTs5nk&feature=player_detailpage
Tuesday, September 25, 2012
Monkey Morality
Sunday, September 16, 2012
Book Tour Events This Fall
California State University, Sacramento
Berkeley, CA
Davis, CA
Palo Alto, CA
Rm. 203, Photonics Center
Sacramento, CA
Thursday, September 13, 2012
The Basics
Approximately 13.7 billion years ago, the universe went from a singularity state of infinite curvature and energy to a rapidly expanding chaotic state, the Big Bang. During the first pico and nano seconds of this period of rapid expansion, the types and behavior of particles that existed rapidly change as the energy levels dropped. Within a few nanoseconds, the kinds of matter and the ways they behave settled into, more or less, the sorts of material constituents we find today. At this point, only hydrogen, helium, and lithium exist. The matter continues to expand outward and eventually, several billion years later, gravitational pull congregates clumps of matter together to form stars. These heat and energy at the cores of these stars cook the early forms of matter, transforming it and creating many of the other, heavier elements on the periodic table. Some of these stars are of sufficient mass to ultimately collapse on themselves, exploding outward and spraying the new elements formed in their cores out into space. That matter eventually coalesces into smaller stars, planets and moons like our own.
Only very recently have one of the hominid species--homo sapiens--on the planet developed cognitive faculties that were sophisticated enough to be able to discover these various facts about the universe. Some of those discoveries are landmarks of vast significance in our develop, although not in a cosmic scale: Darwin’s The Origin of Species is published in 1859. In 1929, Edwin Hubble published his paper, “A Relation Between Distance and Radial Velocity Among Extra-Galactic Nebulae,” in which he showed that the universe is expanding. Extrapolating backward from its rate of expansion made it possible to date the explosive beginning of the universe at approximately 13.7 billion years ago. In 1953, James D. Watson and Francis Crick published their discovery of DNA in Nature: “A Structure of Deoxyrobose Nucleic Acid.”
- The Big Bang occurred 13.7 billion years ago.
- Only hydrogen, helium, and lithium exist for millions of years until large stars form and create many of the other, heavier elements on the periodic table.
- Some of these stars go supernova and distribute these new elements into space.
- That matter eventually coalesces into smaller stars, planets and moons like our own.
- The Earth formed about 4.5 billion years ago.
- Life in the form of the simplest, self-replicating molecules occurs on Earth around 4 billion years ago.
- Once there is replication, natural selection and random mutations over billions of years lead to the evolution of more and more life forms, many of them of increasing levels of complexity.
- Dinosaurs live from about 208 million years ago to 65 million years ago.
- Life on the planet goes through several mass extinctions.
- The Cambrian explosion—a rapid proliferation of the kinds and numbers of living organisms on the planet, occurs about 540 million years ago.
- Mammals begin to expand and diversify significantly about 54 million years ago.
- Modern humans (homo sapiens) originated in Africa about 200,000 years ago.
- Human religious behavior starts approximately 300,000 years ago.
Tuesday, September 11, 2012
Atheism and the Case Against Christ, now available.
It's available at Amazon here.
In the coming weeks I'll be giving talks at UC Berkeley, Stanford, CSUS, UC Davis, and for Sacramento and Bay area atheist groups. I'll post details here as they are firmed up.
Monday, August 27, 2012
It's Out!
Prometheus tells me that they've received my book from the printer and it's going out now. They have it here: Atheism and the Case Against Christ
Wednesday, August 15, 2012
Atheism and the Case Against Christ comes out late Aug. to mid Sept.
The publisher says it will be out in 3-4 weeks!
Wednesday, July 25, 2012
Publication date pushed back
Hi all. First, thanks so much for all my readers who have ordered the book and who are anxious to read it, including the eager apologists. Publishing a book is a long and complicated process. I've been working on final revisions, editing, corrections, and proofreading for months. The index is done finally and sent off to Prometheus. From what they tell me, it's going to be several more weeks to get the final version printed up and shipped out. So please hang on--it's coming.
Matt McCormick
Thursday, June 7, 2012
Disagreeing about Religious Disagreements
Reasonable Religious Disagreements
He endorses this view after considering several alternatives:
After examining this evidence, I find in myself an inclination, perhaps a strong inclination, to think that this evidence supports P. It may even be that I can’t help but believe P. But I see that another person, every bit as sensible and serious as I, has an opposing reaction. Perhaps this person has some bit of evidence that cannot be shared or perhaps he takes the evidence differently than I do. It’s difficult to know everything about his mental life and thus difficult to tell exactly why he believes as he does. One of us must be making some kind of mistake or failing to see some truth. But I have no basis for thinking that the one making the mistake is him rather than me. And the same is true of him. And in that case, the right thing for both of us to do is to suspend judgment on P.
That is, he rejects the widely held notion that it is possible for epistemic peers to share their evidence and reasonably maintain their own beliefs and think that the other party remains reasonable. You've got to give up your view and retreat to suspension of judgment in the face of an epistemic peer who considers the evidence and still disagrees with you, and she should do likewise. Notice also that Feldman gives some considerable creedence to the notion that someone could have a piece of unsharable evidence.
On Feldman's scheme, when the positive atheist is confronted by a theist, call her Smith, the atheist might conclude that Smith is not an epistemic peer because she is not "equal with respect to intelligence, reasoning powers, background information, etc." Starting with the last one first, the atheist might hope to convince Smith by getting her up to speed on the relevant background information. Or Smith might hope to improve Smith's reasoning powers or skills. The atheist may not be able to do much about Smith's lack of intelligence, of course.
The obvious point is that the atheist must acknowledge the disagreement may be the result of the fact that that he, the atheist, is lacking with respect to intelligence, reasoning, powers, background information, etc. The atheist, just like everyone else, must take great care in the face of disagreement to not simply assume that the fault lies on the other side. It's hard to know whether atheists or theists are more prone to this assumption of epistemic superiority mistake. In general, the evidence that shows that belief in God is negatively correlated with education, intelligence, and analytical skill does seem to tilt the situation in the atheist's favor. But that general evidence doesn't show that any particular atheist or his position is not the result of some epistemic mistake or problem. Individuals and the reasonableness of their views must be treated individually.
It seems to me that there's something wrong with Feldman's Modest Skeptical Alternative account in the end. He's rushing to suspend judgment too readily. Perhaps that's because he's lacking some background information with regard to religious disagreements. Having been a student in several of his graduate seminars in epistemology, I certainly won't argue that he's not equal with respect to intelligence or reasoning powers.
I have a couple of half baked ideas here: I am worried that the powerful human propensity to construct complicated and sophisticated rationalizations for some view out of motivated reasoning can give the illusion that someone is an epistemic peer, or that her view warrants more epistemic respect than it deserves. (This worry should plague you about your own views as much as about someone who disagrees with you.)
More specifically, the religious urge is powerful and neurobiological, much more so than some commensurate skeptical or atheist urge. And the propensity towards sophisticated motivated reasoning feeds into the religious urge. So we have a population of cognitive agents where religious mistakes defended with elaborate rationalizations are the widespread norm. Given human psychological constitution, we should expect to find a lot of impressive reasoning in favor of belief. In Feldman's terms, I think what that piece of information should do is show that the bar for taking a believer to be an epistemic peer is higher. (Yes, I know how prejudicial that sounds.) The case is comparable for astrology. If Smith finds out that Jones believes in astrology, even if Jones gives what sounds like a sophisticated, and thoughtful justification for it, Smith ought to be reluctant to conclude that Jones is an epistemic peer. Jones' belief should act as a defeater to the presumption of Jones' being equal with regard to intelligence, reasoning powers, or background information. It's not that Jones cannot vindicate herself or her belief; it's just that the belief, in the context of the rest of what we know about the world and ourselves as cognitive agents, is very strong evidence that something's gone wrong on one or more of those three qualifications for being an epistemic peer.
Feldman, citing van Inwagen, says that belief in astrology is simply indefensible. I agree. Nevertheless, enthusiastic belief in it is widespread, and elaborate justifications are common. In the case of astrology, my assumption is that if an adult endorses it, then he or she is most certainly lacking in background information, reasoning or analytical ability, or intelligence. The only difference I can see with religious belief is that a bigger percentage of the population endorses it.
And now I see more clearly why atheists have the reputation for being smug and superior assholes. Feldman, to his credit, is urging us to not go down that road. But I don't see how it can be avoided.
Another way to put the point is to consider the larger populations of cognitive agents we are dealing with. For virtually any idea, it is possible to find someone who believes it, who appears to be reasonable and thoughtful, and who is in possession of the relevant background information. John Mack, infamous Harvard psychiatrist, vigorously defended the claim for many years that aliens were visiting the Earth, abducting humans, and conducting bizarre medical experiments on them. Strange ideas are too seductive to human psychology, and there are too many of us. There are thoughtful, intelligent, seemingly reasonable people who deny evolution, who believe in witchcraft, who believe that alien spacecraft are responsible for crop circles, who believe that Bigfoot is real, and so on. If we apply Feldman's principle, then it would appear that we should suspend judgment about all of these matters. And that result suggests that his principle encourages suspension of judgment about matters that are clearly reasonable to believe given the evidence.
Tuesday, May 8, 2012
Monday, April 30, 2012
Thinking Analytically Leads to Religious Disbelief
In a recent issue of Science: Analytic Thinking Promotes Religious Disbelief, by Will M. Gervais and Ara Norenzayan:
Scientific interest in the cognitive underpinnings of religious belief has grown in recent years. However, to date, little experimental research has focused on the cognitive processes that may promote religious disbelief. The present studies apply a dual-process model of cognitive processing to this problem, testing the hypothesis that analytic processing promotes religious disbelief. Individual differences in the tendency to analytically override initially flawed intuitions in reasoning were associated with increased religious disbelief. Four additional experiments provided evidence of causation, as subtle manipulations known to trigger analytic processing also encouraged religious disbelief. Combined, these studies indicate that analytic processing is one factor (presumably among several) that promotes religious disbelief. Although these findings do not speak directly to conversations about the inherent rationality, value, or truth of religious beliefs, they illuminate one cognitive factor that may influence such discussions.
Monday, March 19, 2012
Tripping Balls
A quick post while I'm on the road climbing. This study of over 13,000 subjects shows amazingly high rates for hallucinations in the general public. The implications for the advent and persistence of religion is obvious:
Prevalence of hallucinations and their pathological associations in the general population
Psychiatry Research
Volume 97, Issue 2 , Pages 153-164, 27 December 2000
Hallucinations are perceptual phenomena involved in many fields of pathology. Although clinically widely explored, studies in the general population of these phenomena are scant. This issue was investigated using representative samples of the non-institutionalized general population of the United Kingdom, Germany and Italy aged 15 years or over (N=13057). These surveys were conducted by telephone and explored mental disorders and hallucinations (visual, auditory, olfactory, haptic and gustatory hallucinations, out-of-body experiences, hypnagogic and hypnopompic hallucinations). Overall, 38.7% of the sample reported hallucinatory experiences (19.6% less than once in a month; 6.4% monthly; 2.7% once a week; and 2.4% more than once a week). These hallucinations occurred, (1) At sleep onset (hypnagogic hallucinations 24.8%) and/or upon awakening (hypnopompic hallucinations 6.6%), without relationship to a specific pathology in more than half of the cases; frightening hallucinations were more often the expression of sleep or mental disorders such as narcolepsy, OSAS or anxiety disorders. (2) During the daytime and reported by 27% of the sample: visual (prevalence of 3.2%) and auditory (0.6%) hallucinations were strongly related to a psychotic pathology (respective OR of 6.6 and 5.1 with a conservative estimate of the lifetime prevalence of psychotic disorders in this sample of 0.5%); and to anxiety (respective OR of 5.0 and 9.1). Haptic hallucinations were reported by 3.1% with current use of drugs as the highest risk factor (OR=9.8). In conclusion, the prevalence of hallucinations in the general population is not negligible. Daytime visual and auditory hallucinations are associated with a greater risk of psychiatric disorders. The other daytime sensory hallucinations are more related to an organic or a toxic disorder.
Wednesday, March 14, 2012
The F Word
I just gave a lecture to Cosumnes River College last night about faith based religious claims. The slides I used are here
Sunday, March 11, 2012
Friday, March 2, 2012
Bias In Religious Thinking, II
I gave a public lecture at UC Davis last night about recent research on bias and its applications to religious thinking. Here's my latest version of the slides.
The student group at UC Davis has posted a video of my talk here: Bias and Heuristics in Religious Thinking
I didn't know about the camera's location, so I paced in and out of frame a lot during the talk. But maybe my explanations of the slide points are useful.
Wednesday, February 22, 2012
Favorite Atheist Blog?
My blog has been nominated for best atheism blog of the year by About.com. Go here to vote if the mood strikes you: http://atheism.about.com/b/2012/02/22/favorite-agnostic-atheist-blog-of-2011.htm
Tuesday, February 14, 2012
What is an Atheist?
The Drew School in San Francisco has invited me to speak as part of a lecture series from religious leaders. I'll be speaking about atheism and tolerance on Wednesday, Feb. 15. My lecture slides are here:
What is Atheism?
Bias in Religious Thinking
Thursday, November 24, 2011
Motivated Religious Reasoning
Thursday, November 17, 2011
More on Motivated Reasoning
Mercier and Sperber give an impressive argument here: Why Do Humans Reason? Arguments for an argumentative theory The standard view of reasoning is that its primary function is correct cognitive functions and find the truth. They argue that it is better understood as facilitating persuasion in social or communication contexts. Their thesis, they maintain, better explains the available evidence that shows how bad humans are at reasoning.
Their section on Motivated Reasoning contains this nice summary of some of the literature. The applications to the sorts of reasoning we frequently see coming from religious believers seeking to defend the God/Jesus conclusion at all costs are striking. For now, all I have time to do is offer a long quote:
Saturday, October 1, 2011
Motivated Reasoning
One of my students (Thanks Kate!) found this article. They are arguing for a thesis quite consistent with what I've been pressing in several recent posts:
