Book review here: http://tech.mit.edu/V132/N57/atheism.html
Friday, November 30, 2012
Wednesday, November 21, 2012
Round Up of Some Research on Religion from Science Daily
Study Explores Distrust of Atheists by Believers
Distrust is the central motivating factor behind why religious people dislike atheists, according to a new study led by University of British Columbia psychologists.
Distrust is the central motivating factor behind why religious people dislike atheists, according to a new study led by University of British Columbia psychologists.
New University of Otago research suggests that when non-religious
people think about their own death they become more consciously skeptical about
religion, but unconsciously grow more receptive to religious belief.
American megachurches use stagecraft, sensory pageantry,
charismatic leadership and an upbeat, unchallenging vision of Christianity to
provide their congregants with a powerful emotional religious experience,
according to research from the University of Washington.
Despite differences in rituals and beliefs among the world's major
religions, spirituality often enhances health regardless of a person's faith,
according to University of Missouri researchers. The MU researchers believe
that health care providers could take advantage of this correlation between
health -- particularly mental health -- and spirituality by tailoring
treatments and rehabilitation programs to accommodate an individual's spiritual
inclinations.
"Love thy neighbor" is preached from many a pulpit. But
new research from the University of California, Berkeley, suggests that the
highly religious are less motivated by compassion when helping a stranger than
are atheists, agnostics and less religious people.
Parental hopes of a "miraculous intervention," prompted
by deeply held religious beliefs, are leading to very sick children being
subjected to futile care and needless suffering, suggests a small study in the Journal of Medical Ethics.
Psychological research has found that religious people feel great
about themselves, with a tendency toward higher social self-esteem and better
psychological adjustment than non-believers. But a new study published in Psychological
Science, a journal of the Association for Psychological Science,
finds that this is only true in countries that put a high value on religion.
Tuesday, November 20, 2012
1, 2, 3, . . . Ready or Not, Here I Come!
I’ve been thinking about the arguments for atheism from
divine hiddenness. Here’s a way to argue
for atheism in that vein with some similarities to Drange and Schellenberg and
with several improvements on the argument of my own.
Imagine two scenarios, both where it would appear that God
is hiding.
Scenario A: God isn’t real and we fail to find good
evidence for supernatural beings.
Suppose that beings humans find themselves in this
situation:
There is no supernatural being of any sort.
Furthermore,
b. none
of the conceptual arguments for supernatural beings are compelling
c. we
have made substantial efforts to uncover supernatural beings.
d. none
of our attempts to discover supernatural beings have succeeded
e. the
available evidence concerning supernatural beings are inadequate.
f. there
is a presumption that supernatural beings are the sort of entity that, if one were
to exist, then it would manifest in some fashion that is detectable by beings
with our cognitive faculties.
g. the
presumption that supernatural beings would manifest in some way has not been
defeated.
h. naturalized
models of supernatural belief formation are well justified by the evidence and
they provide a better alternative account of the origins of supernatural
beliefs.
Question: What is the reasonable conclusion to draw
about supernatural beings in this situation?
Would non-belief be epistemically inculpable in this
situation? That is, if humans conclude that there are no supernatural
beings, would that conclusion be unwarranted?
What about believing in a supernatural being? And would being an agnostic be epistemically
culpable or inculpable in this situation?
It seems to me for a number of reasons that disbelief in
supernatural beings would be justified. Disbelief
would not be epistemically culpable. Furthermore,
believing in a supernatural being in this situation would be epistemically
culpable and irrational. I even think
that being agnostic in this situation, particularly given the point in h.,
would be unreasonable/culpable.
That is:
Belief in situation A:
irrational.
Agnosticism in situation A:
irrational.
Disbelief in situation A:
reasonable/rational.
Scenario B: God is Real, but Hiding
Suppose that humans find themselves in this situation:
God exists and possesses the power and the knowledge to make
himself known to humans.
Yet for reasons unknown to humans, God insures that:
a. there
are no empirical indications of God
b. none
of the conceptual arguments for God is compelling
c. we
have made substantial efforts to uncover God,
d. none
of our attempts to discover God have succeeded
e. the
available evidence concerning God is inadequate.
f. there
is a presumption that God is the sort of entity that, if God were to exist,
then God would manifest in some fashion that is detectable by beings with our
cognitive faculties.
g. the
presumption that supernatural beings/God would manifest in some way has not
been defeated.
h. naturalized
models of supernatural belief formation are well justified by the evidence and
they provide a better alternative account of the origins of supernatural
beliefs.
Question: What is the reasonable conclusion to draw
about supernatural beings in this situation?
Would disbelief be epistemically inculpable in this
situation? That is, if humans conclude that there are no supernatural
beings, would that conclusion be unwarranted? Notice that the evidential situation for humans is exactly the same in both scenarios. So the answers to our questions about what is the reasonable conclusion to draw must be the same, with some interesting side notes. Ironically, despite the fact that God is real in this situation, it
seems to me that disbelief, given the evidential situation would be
justified. That is, the atheist in the
world where God is real but hiding, would have a well-justified but false
belief. We couldn’t find epistemic fault
with the conclusion that this atheist has drawn. The apocryphal story about Bertrand Russell
is relevant. After a lecture about atheism,
a member of the audience asked him, “Prof. Russell, what are you going to do
after you die and then in the afterlife you show up at the Pearly Gates and God
and Saint Peter are all there and it’s obvious how wrong you are?” Allegedly without missing a step, Russell
said he’d say to God, “Not enough evidence, God! Not enough evidence!”
Furthermore, if someone were to believe in God in this
situation, it would be irrational and unjustified. Ironically, she would happen to get it
right. That is, she’d have a true belief. But her evidence did not justify her
conclusion. Her belief would have all
the virtue of thievery over honest toil, to quote Russell again. She’d be like a psychic who accidentally
predicted the winning lottery numbers.
Her getting the numbers right by accident doesn’t vindicate her method
or improve the reliability of her method of derivation.
Furthermore, if agnosticism was unreasonable and unjustified
in scenario A, it would be here too.
That is, the agnostic who suspends judgment in scenario B, where a-h are
also true, would be unjustified.
The interesting question here concerns the reasonable limits
to agnosticism. Under what circumstances
should one be an agnostic. It seems to
me that a-h, if they are true, are enough to warrant moving from agnostic to
atheism. Some other examples are
suggestive: Suppose we insert Bigfoot or
Leprechauns into scenario A.
Suppose there are no Leprechauns. And suppose further that we have searched diligently,
no compelling evidence in their favor has been found, Leprechauns are the sorts
of things that would be revealed in some way to our cognitive faculties if we
were to search and encounter them, and furthermore, we have other natural
explanations of why people have believed in Leprechauns. In that situation, you should not be
agnostic. Being agnostic would be
irrational.
Many agnostics have the view that God is not like
Leprechauns, so there is a disanalogy here.
God is unlike Leprechauns in ways that require us to be agnostic about
him, but atheist about the Leprechauns.
I think there could be a plausible argument here, but I’m not sure. The central issue for these agnostics, I
think, would be to deny that condition g. has been met in the case of God. There are good reasons to think that the
presumption about God’s manifesting to our cognitive faculties in h. is
defeated in the case of God but not in the case of Leprechauns.
The really interesting question to me right now is, what are
those reasons that defeat the presumption?
Why should we think that God is not the sort of thing that would be
manifest to our cognitive faculties in any of the relevant ways? Pretty clearly, on lots of theistic
hypotheses, God is the sort of thing whose existence or non-existence makes
some manifest difference in the world.
The world or the arguments, would look different if there were no God in
some way that we could discern. The
existence of gods of that sort is undermined by this argument. But if there were a supernatural being whose
presence or absence would not be manifest to our cognitive faculties, then our
not finding any manifestations would not be adequate grounds to conclude that
no such being exists.
This agnostic might argue for this thesis: There may yet be some sort of supernatural
being that we can have no cognitive access to and that we can form no positive
thesis about. We should be agnostic
about that being because the absence
of evidence for it isn’t indicative either way about its existence.
My question here is this:
What exactly are we being agnostic about in this case? Which hypothesis am I suspending judgment
about? Is it this: there may yet be some truths about which I can
form no idea, I can have no comprehension, and that elude my cognitive
faculties altogether.
It doesn’t seem to me that suspending judgment is the right way to describe the attitude we
should take about those proposals. We
should suspend judgment, it seems to me, about whether there are extra
terrestrial forms of life in our universe.
That is a clear proposal about which our evidence is split or about
which we do not have enough evidence yet to draw a conclusion. The mercurial transcendental entity that the
agnostic proposes is utterly unlike alien life.
We have no access, and we can have no access, perhaps in principle, to
such an entity. It would seem that we
cannot hope to form any sort of propositional attitude at all about it, not
even enough to suspend judgment about it. Furthermore, it is relevant to point
out that this agnostic is taking a conservative attitude about the possibility
of something that is utterly unlike any of the divine beings that are typically
proposed or believed in. This agnostic
seems to have tacitly agreed that in situation A or B, the only reasonable
conclusion is to be atheist, not agnostic, about the overwhelming majority of
the gods that humans have believed in.
This agnostic is a very wide atheist, but not quite as wide as the
widest atheist. It just not clear to me
that suspending judgment in this case even makes sense or is the epistemically
responsible position.
Monday, November 19, 2012
Thursday, November 15, 2012
Do We Need Religious Belief for Happiness and Emotional Security?
I'm pressed for time, so this is just going to be a brief note with some ideas that I need to develop later. It's widely believed by theists, skeptics, and atheists alike that religious belief serves an indispensable emotional function by giving people a sense of hope, emotional security, and happiness. So despite all of the powerful arguments in favor of atheism, or at least undermining objections to theism, that doubters present, this response recurs: "Ok sure, the reasons for believing in the resurrection, God, or other gods are lousy, but what's wrong with someone who still believes, keeps it to themselves, and who derives some personal contentment and emotional security from it? Why do you have to pick on them?"
Here's the thing: First, it's not at all clear that the widely accepted link between believing and emotional benefits is true. Phil Zuckerman, a sociologist at Pitzer College, has been arguing on the basis of secularism in northern Europe that nonbelievers are actually happier.
Here are a few sources:
Atheism: Contemporary Rates and Patterns
Here's a video of Zuckerman:
Zuckerman: Atheists, Agnostics, and the Irreligious
Here's Zuckerman on bias and discrimination against atheists in the U.S.: Washington Post: Why Do Americans Still Dislike Atheists?
Do we need God to have a happy society?
Second, humans are notoriously bad at predicting or knowing what will make them happy. See Dan Gilbert, Stumbling on Happiness Ask people what the effects of a horrible accident or losing a loved one will be on them and they will estimate the effects as much more devastating than they actually are when those traumas occur. Our basic levels of happiness, contentment, and personal satisfaction reassert themselves in time, even after events in our lives that we estimate will have a long, irreversible negative effect on us.
So it seems to me that these two issues need to be connected and that we need to re-evaluate the alleged emotional and pragmatic justification for religious believing. If Zuckerman is right, then it appears that there isn't even a emotional justification for believing. Getting rid of religious belief might, contrary to what people think, make us happier, healthier, and more emotionally content.
Thursday, November 1, 2012
Stanford Event: The F Word
A link to details about my Nov. 8 speaking event:
McCormick Lecture: Stanford University
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)